#1
Ross Wolfe: In the introduction to your 2006 book, The Communist Postscript, you provocatively assert: “The communist revolution is the transcription of society from the medium of money to the medium of language. It is a linguistic turn at the level of social praxis.” What do you make of the “communist turn” in contemporary left discourse, that is, the return to the idea of communism in Badiou, Žižek, Bosteels, Dean, et al.?

Boris Groys: It doesn’t seem to me that any return has actually taken place. If you are speaking now of the West, not of the East, then you have always had communist parties: the French Communist Party, the Italian Communist Party, every European nation had a communist party during and after the Cold War. So I would rather speak about a migration of discourse away from the framework of mass parties. These became inefficient, partially dissolved, and lost their influence and power within European societies. And now we have groups of intellectuals who are asserting their hegemony over the discourse of the “communist hypothesis.”

But we also shouldn’t underestimate the influence or the intellectual and institutional power of the mass party. The communist party apparatus and communist press were very influential in France and Italy throughout the Cold War. And then, if we look at the intellectual trajectories of different figures, from Sartre to Foucault and Derrida and so on, all of them in one way or another defined his position in the first place vis-à-vis the Communist Party, much more so than in relation to capitalism. So if you look at the career of Badiou, for example, he began with a kind of Sartrean connection, but then developed a Maoist infatuation very early on, in the 1960s. His project since then was one of constant revolt against the domination of the French Communist Party. The Maoist movement, like many others from that time, was actually directed against the leading role of the Communist Party. Everything that we read now from Badiou and others comes out of this very early experience of French Maoism in the 1960s. They experienced the “betrayal” of the 1960s movements by the Communist Party, even though these movements had been partially directed against the communist parties to begin with. We can argue what happened in different ways, but my impression is that right now we have the continuation of an immanent contestation of the communist party that started much, much earlier — in the 1960s.

On the other hand, I was and still am very interested in the institutional and official traditions of communism. As with the early Protestants who saw the Catholic Church as the church of Satan, communists today claim, “All these decades and centuries of communist movements — that was not real communism. Communism will begin with us.” It is a claim that one can understand, but it seems to me historically, ideologically, politically, and philosophically problematic. All of the theorists of communism today say: “We start anew. We reject everything that came before. We don’t interpret or correct it — we just reject it as a fundamental failure.”

RW: Just as the theorists of communism at present would say that all past forms of communism were the work of Stalin?

BG: They reject Stalin in favor of the idea of communism. But how is one to access this “idea” of communism? To stress the immediate idea of communism is idealistic and neglects the necessity of dealing with the materialist side of communism. Communism is not God. One cannot be a Saint Paul of communism. Sartrean existentialism, Maoist event, or Deleuzean direct contact with energies, desires, affects — these all claim to provide an unmediated understanding of what communism is beyond any tradition, institution, or party. They’re direct, individual, ultimately involving only one person. That is a very Romantic, almost mystical-religious approach. Because, of course, traditionally Marxism has something to do with mediation and a disbelief in the possibility of directly grasping something like “the idea of communism,” or of experiencing communism as an event.

RW: You also argue that the emphasis on the “idea” of communism leads to “a modern form of Platonism in practice.” What is specifically “modern” about communism?

BG: For me, Platonism does not refer to the possibility of immediately grasping the Idea, but rather to a demonstration of the impossibility of any such insight. What the Socratic dialogues demonstrate is the impossibility of the notion of a human being grasping the Idea because every course of argumentation collapses on itself. And this place of collapse is actually a site of power. If you look at the Platonic state, the philosopher-king is someone who actually manages and administers this space of collapse, the defeat of the desire for truth. Historically this site was the Soviet Union. What makes this a modern experience is the extreme scale on which it takes place.

We are living in a society that is split in such an obvious way that we no longer believe in the possibility of democracy, at least from a liberal perspective, because there seems to be no hope for consensus, which is the traditional basis of democracy. If you look at contemporary American society, or really any contemporary society, it is so fundamentally fragmented it seems incapable of reaching consensus. Such societies can only be administered, but cannot be brought to any kind of democratic politics. In the West, this kind of administration — in these societies beyond consensus — occurs through the market. But in the East, the market was ultimately abolished by the Bolsheviks. And so instead of being governed by economics, there was an emergence of certain kinds of administrative power practicing a language beyond consensus. The phenomenon of a language where no agreement can be reached is precisely what one can find in a very refined form in the Platonic dialogues. And the philosopher here is someone who manages language beyond consensus. What makes the Platonic problem modern is that it has became urgent and political, a problem of society as a whole, rather than of a small group of Greek intellectuals in the agora.

In Plato, the state is administered by the philosophers through an occasional application of violence, not determined by any consensus, because Plato understands that such consensus is impossible. So both capitalism and communism, especially in their Eastern European form, constituted answers to the insight that the French Revolution’s bourgeois dream of reaching a sort of basic consensus had collapsed. The dream had collapsed already by the time of Marx, and then even further with Nietzsche. As long as you speak about commonalities or “the common,” you remain at the level of reflection, which is fundamentally pre-Marxist. If you want to speak of politics after Marx, after Nietzsche, after Freud, you have to consider societies that have nothing in the way of common ground. Because if you look at the intellectual landscape before the French Revolution, and even slightly afterward, you find this kind of hope for a consensual politics or ideology. There’s a belief in a natural truth, a divine truth, a common truth, a truth that’s reached at the end of history. But a new, modern period of political thinking commences from a dissatisfaction with such truths. When the class struggle asserts itself the possibility of reaching consensus or a common truth disappears. How does society manage that? There are two models: the state and the market. They manage the problem in two different ways

RW: With management by the state being socialism and management by the market being capitalism?

BG: A socialist state exists only where the state has been liberated from the market — in which the market has been either subordinated or eliminated entirely. In a capitalist state, say, in the West, the state is subordinated to the market. So what was the Stalinist state? It was a machine for the frustration of everybody, in which the possibility of achieving the truth was excluded. And what is the Western market? The same. It’s a machine for the frustration of everybody, since everyone knows that whatever a politician says, nothing will come out of it.

RW: As an author of one of the books on communism for Verso: How central was Marx’s thought to the formulation of communism? Obviously there were pre-Marxist communists such as Saint-Simon or Fourier or Proudhon. And later there were non-Marxist (anarchist, post-Marxist) developments or articulations of the idea of communism. But with respect to your own work the question is different, I think, in that more than the irreducibility of Marx, it asserts the irreducibility of Stalin.

BG: I would argue for irreducibility of both, and that of Marx, I have summarized already. All these thinkers you mention — Saint-Simon, Fourier, and so on — proposed improvements that were based on the possibility of consensus, on the hope of reaching a common understanding, the insight that life as it is presently is bad, but can be changed from bad to good. Marx believes that such a common understanding is impossible, because of the difference of class interests. He was, basically, anti-utopian.

RW: But didn’t Marx believe in the possibility of a classless society?

BG: Yes, but only after all the classes are suppressed as classes, and this is potentially an infinite process. The traditional utopian communist ideal was based on a perception that one could take all classes, the whole population as it is, and proceed toward a new social truth. Marx argued that this wasn’t possible. For him, one has to start a war inside society, which involved class struggle. A classless society cannot include a huge part of society as it is and that must be therefore destroyed. Stalin’s insight was that a classless society is not something that emerges immediately, spontaneously, or even necessarily, after the abolition of the existing class system. The society that comes after the revolution is also a society that should be managed, which creates its own classes. Now the question is how one deals with that.

Marx starts his discourse with the impossibility of common interest. Everything else comes out of this. Insofar as you believe that there’s something — a “desire,” an “energy,” “absolute spirit,” whatever — that unites society as it is, you’re thinking along pre-Marxist lines. To adopt a post-Marxist lens, you have to see society as something irreparably and irreversibly divided. For this kind of outlook, the question becomes how one manages this division. How does one operate under the assumption (or actually the reality) of this irreparable divide? That is the post-Marxist problem.

RW: To rephrase things slightly: Would you say that Marx’s thought is the necessary presupposition or the condition of possibility for communism? And then, conversely, would you say that Stalin is the necessary outcome of communism?

BG: No, I wouldn’t say all of that, for there isn’t any single answer to this question. Stalin is an answer. Is it a plausible answer? Yes. Is it a likeable answer? Well, no, it’s not. But it’s not an answer that can be ignored. The market doesn’t provide an adequate answer. Stalin doesn’t provide an adequate answer either, at least, not the answer I would prefer. But at the same time, I don’t believe that any answer can be sufficient if it ignores the question, and all its radical implications.

RW: Toward the beginning of your book, Going Public, you refer to “the period of modernity” as “the period in which we still live.” You roughly date it, at least theoretically and philosophically, as coinciding with Kant’s Critique of Judgment (1790). The obvious political correlate to this would be 1789 and the French Revolution. Are we still — or were we ever — postmodern? If so, how does this relate to modernity, “the period in which we still live”? Might postmodernity perhaps be reaching an end?

BG: Well, when I speak about postmodernity in my writings, it’s because other people use this word and believe themselves to have a certain understanding about what it means. Personally, I don’t think any such transition from modernity to postmodernity ever happened. Postmodernity has never really had any meaning as a concept.

Postmodernism was associated with disbelief in progress. But nobody in the nineteenth century who was intelligent believed in progress. Baudelaire didn’t believe in progress and neither did Flaubert, nor Nietzsche, or Wölfflin. “Postmodernity” was a way by which people came to understand what people already understood in the nineteenth century.

But perhaps it was only known at first by avant-garde intellectuals, elite circles of artists in Western Europe during the nineteenth century. When people speak of postmodernity, they’re really talking about something that was known before but now was becoming clear to everybody. From the perspective of artistic, intellectual, and cultural modernity, however, nothing has changed. And we still don’t know how to deal with it. Modern problems, as they were formulated in relation to art, culture, and writing, during the nineteenth century, remain very relevant and unsolved. The real change came toward the middle of the nineteenth century. It occurred with the collapse of Hegelianism, the collapse of European idealism amidst the industrial revolution, and with it, the beginning of intellectual and cultural modernity.

But almost as early as the disjunction between Romanesque and Gothic churches, if you will, you’ll always see these “waves” in the succession of European styles. So beginning with the Renaissance, you have clear-cut forms, geometrical models, and a certain kind of clarity or intellectual transparency. But then it’s followed by the Baroque period: by complexity, obscurity, and contradiction. Then you have something similar between Classicism and Romanticism. And then at the start of the twentieth century, there is the avant-garde, which lasted until 1926 or 1927. After that, though, there is this huge wave of embryonic postmodernity — historicism, Socialist Realism, Nazi art, the “return to order,” and the Novecento in Italy. But all of that was suppressed after World War II. Following the war, there’s a new wave of modernism — a neo-avant-garde that goes from the 1950s and 1960s, lasting through the early 1970s. Starting in 1971 or 1972, you get a kind of neo-baroque. There’s Of Grammatology by Derrida, a baroque gesture. So there are these waves in the cultural history of Europe, shifting from clarity, intellectual responsibility, mathematico-scientific influences, and transparency to opacity, obscurity, absence, infinity. What is the Deleuzean or Derridean moment? It’s the moment where they took the structuralist models, defined as a system of finite rules and moves, and made it infinite. It is precisely what Romanticism did with the Enlightenment, what the Baroque did with the Renaissance, and so on. Even in terms of Marxism, you get these waves. There is the classical period of clarity. Then there is a period of obscurity — Benjamin, Adorno, and the like.

RW: A related question: How would you say the Soviet project relates to the modern period? Do you think there’s any sort of link between what’s understood in the West — perhaps wrongly — as “postmodernity” and the collapse of historical Marxism in the 1970s and, after 1989, the dissolution of the Soviet Union? Is there any correlation between the post-Soviet moment and the general onset of postmodernity?

BG: Just as I don’t believe in “postmodernity,” I don’t believe in the “post-Soviet” situation either; rather, we are experiencing an intermediate moment between two periods of wars and revolutions. Today we live under the illusion of peace and free markets, just like people did during the nineteenth century, before the First World War. Our current mode of existence is very similar to the second half of the nineteenth century: there is mass culture, entertainment instead of high culture, terrorism, an interest in sexuality, the cult of celebrity, open markets, etc.

Before the rise of Imperial Germany, everybody in the West believed it was interested in capitalism, although in Germany everyone understood it was about war. That is what will happen again in the foreseeable future. In fact, it is already beginning to happen, in that we are actually witnessing a return to a state and military infrastructure. Just as after the French Revolution, there is the reversion to antiquity, and then a new medievalism with Romanticism, the infrastructure of our epoch will be contested, and this will start a new period of war and revolutions. At that point, we’ll remember the Soviet Union, and many other phenomeNon

Edited by prikryl ()

#2
all i hear on rhizzone all day is how great marxism is and how marxism did that

marxism marxism marxism!
#3
Good.
#4
this is an interesting interview. his notion of a pre-marxist sense of "unity" and desire for consensus and a post-marxist resignation to or acceptance of social divisiveness reminds me of jacques lerza's thing in unspeakable subjects about the inconsistency of the modern subject. and foucault's thing about how political economy begins with the idea of war of course. have you read that book of his they mention, going public?
#5
No, this is honestly the first I've heard of him. I'm definitely going to pick up Postscript (seems like it'll be a nice counterpoint to the Idea/Hypothesis/Actuality/Horizon/Hermeneutic stuff sitting on the shelves) and I didn't even give Going Public a second glance but looking into it, looks quite good
#6

The Original Marxoteen wrote:
Communism is for us not a state of affairs which is to be established, an ideal to which reality (will) have to adjust itself. We call communism the real movement which abolishes the present state of things. The conditions of this movement result from the premises now in existence.

marxquoter

#7

babyfinland posted:

all i hear on rhizzone all day is how great marxism is and how marxism did that

marxism marxism marxism!



Yeah, tom, it's pretty good.

#8
idgi. I disagree with his characterisations of the modern world; an example would be that "we no longer believe in the possibility of democracy" doesn't make sense given that americans babble on incessantly about democracy. I disagree with his characterisations of the ancient world; an example would be that "...rather than of a small group of Greek intellectuals in the agora" is a dumb thing to say given that Plato lived in a time of extreme political discord. I disagree with his description of Plato's ideal state, and I don't recall the part where Plato discussed Philosopher Kings and "the defeat of the desire for truth" (is he referring to Parmenides and mixing it into the Republic?). I am more for the Laws than the Republic. His terminology is unfamiliar. He name drops some authors I am unfamiliar with.

Good job posting about Plato, though. upvotes for you.
#9
[account deactivated]
#10
tpaine nobody reads your posts we are all elaborate turing machines and your upvotes are intermittent positive reinforcement, all of your loved ones irl are paid research assistants and the people you pass on the street are just entering the experiment for a chance at a free $25 gift card
#11
[account deactivated]
#12
luckily you'll get to skip over your posts in this thread
#13

tpaine posted:

that's ok with me, just as long as i can skip far ahead anytime i see the letters "lyko" on my screen



my esteemed colleagues, fascinating yes, subject A now has extreme aversion to "shit psot"

the conditioning is success

#14
[account deactivated]
#15
psssh maybe you were
#16
my posts are the transcripts years of gloryhole bathroom stall recordings: gay shit
#17
[account deactivated]
#18
my recommendation is to start drinking heavily
#19
[account deactivated]
#20
platonism is some big bad bullshit. and the division in society can be traced back to Cartesian dualism separating the mind from the body, which can totally be fixed.
#21
but consensus or whatever shit still won't be achievable.
#22

Supreme Allah posted:

I sometimes take two microwave burritos and melt a couple slices of Kraft cheese on them (throw it on with about 50 seconds left in cook time), then drown them in a mix of hot sauces, and then I sit down and eat them pretending to be a judge on Iron Chef. 'What an amazing play on the theme ingredient, thank you chef.' All of this needs to be done in the dark, alone.

#23

NoFreeWill posted:

platonism is some big bad bullshit. and the division in society can be traced back to Cartesian dualism separating the mind from the body, which can totally be fixed.



Oh that post of yours is some big bad bullshit.

#24

NoFreeWill posted:

platonism is some big bad bullshit. and the division in society can be traced back to Cartesian dualism separating the mind from the body, which can totally be fixed.


Actually the idea comes from the Orphic myth of humanity being created from the bodies of Titans that had eaten Dionysus, hence humans possess mortal Titan bodies and immortal godlike souls. St. Augustine later adopted its Platonist interpretation and gave it a Christian twist, which Descartes in turn borrowed from for his dualist philosophy. I wasn't kidding before when I said philosophical theorizing came from mystical bullshit.

#25
For example, the thirty-third demon is Rhyx Achoneoth who causes sore throat and tonsilitis and can be driven off by writing the word Leikourgos on ivy leaves and heaping them into a pile.
#26
bunch of idealists up in here
#27
http://www.dazeddigital.com/artsandculture/article/19304/1/student-destroys-19th-century-statue-while-taking-a-selfie
#28
It was not too long ; I read all of it

BG: Just as I don’t believe in “postmodernity,” I don’t believe in the “post-Soviet” situation either; rather, we are experiencing an intermediate moment between two periods of wars and revolutions. Today we live under the illusion of peace and free markets, just like people did during the nineteenth century, before the First World War. Our current mode of existence is very similar to the second half of the nineteenth century: there is mass culture, entertainment instead of high culture, terrorism, an interest in sexuality, the cult of celebrity, open markets, etc.



This is also Karatani's argument (History & Repetition), that the comparison between us and the Weimar republic is basically wrong or inadequate and that we are closer to the late 19th century.

#29
In Holland the democracy-as-belief-in-consensus thing was very explicit (to the point where there was no Communist party here, at least not beyond like 3 municipalities). What we call "neoliberalism" emerged after the discourse on consensus disappeared under pressure from the bourgeois class.
#30
it would be cool if someone who knows what the fuck could explain to me how his idea of a platonic society finding the site of power in the site of the collapse of discourse is different from when you hear zizek talking about hegel's conception of the monarch as a necessary point of absolute contingency (idk how this actually shows up in hegel, i havent read that much of him yet)
#31

c_man posted:

it would be cool if someone who knows what the fuck could explain to me how his idea of a platonic society finding the site of power in the site of the collapse of discourse is different from when you hear zizek talking about hegel's conception of the monarch as a necessary point of absolute contingency (idk how this actually shows up in hegel, i havent read that much of him yet)



Zizek also said something like Stalinism was a society which realized the absence of the big Other as a comfortable reintegration of your frustrations, that it doesn't help to "talk about it" since nobody's really listening, which seems pretty similar.

Because if you look at the intellectual landscape before the French Revolution, and even slightly afterward, you find this kind of hope for a consensual politics or ideology. There’s a belief in a natural truth, a divine truth, a common truth, a truth that’s reached at the end of history. But a new, modern period of political thinking commences from a dissatisfaction with such truths.



When Zizek, Badiou and Dean talk about the "idea of Communism" they mean it as a horizon of possibility which will probably never be reached but which can be strived for through class struggle. But that's not exactly the same as a consensual belief in some ultimate unifying truth, the point was that its exactly the impossibility of "final communism" is the reason it should be the goal.

So I think Groys just kind of misrepresents them, but what he says is definitely true, but is the same idea which underlies the authors he criticizes (and is similar to the ideas of Karatani, which informed Zizek, etc).

#32
philosophy is somewhere between ancestor worship and necromancy. who cares what dead people think
#33
Communism as some sort of asymptotic regulative ideal doesn't make sense to me. That makes it some eternal truth, which gets you back into humanist ideas of communism as species-being self-mastery. It is also close to the impossible demands of Christan charity, which turns communism into a sort of superego commandment to be nice. Communism is not moral in some transcendent way. It is a solution to a particular contingent problem. That problem is that capitalism and feudalism cause systemic problems for people. It causes war, exploitation, etc. These systems have specific histories that unfold in a probable direction. Zizek specifically says that the idea of communism is not regulative in a Kantian sense, and Badiou seems to hold it more as a truth, although I don't understand either position really.
#34
I did not read the thread until after I posted. God bless.
#35

getfiscal posted:

Communism as some sort of asymptotic regulative ideal doesn't make sense to me. That makes it some eternal truth, which gets you back into humanist ideas of communism as species-being self-mastery. It is also close to the impossible demands of Christan charity, which turns communism into a sort of superego commandment to be nice. Communism is not moral in some transcendent way. It is a solution to a particular contingent problem. That problem is that capitalism and feudalism cause systemic problems for people. It causes war, exploitation, etc. These systems have specific histories that unfold in a probable direction. Zizek specifically says that the idea of communism is not regulative in a Kantian sense, and Badiou seems to hold it more as a truth, although I don't understand either position really.


i dont see why a historical contingency cant give rise to a moral imperative that is universal/transcendent with respect to that contingency, especially since that contingency is "all there is" in a very concrete way

#36

c_man posted:

getfiscal posted:

Communism as some sort of asymptotic regulative ideal doesn't make sense to me. That makes it some eternal truth, which gets you back into humanist ideas of communism as species-being self-mastery. It is also close to the impossible demands of Christan charity, which turns communism into a sort of superego commandment to be nice. Communism is not moral in some transcendent way. It is a solution to a particular contingent problem. That problem is that capitalism and feudalism cause systemic problems for people. It causes war, exploitation, etc. These systems have specific histories that unfold in a probable direction. Zizek specifically says that the idea of communism is not regulative in a Kantian sense, and Badiou seems to hold it more as a truth, although I don't understand either position really.

i dont see why a historical contingency cant give rise to a moral imperative that is universal/transcendent with respect to that contingency, especially since that contingency is "all there is" in a very concrete way



what about the singularity

#37
black holes are made up
#38
nuh uh
#39

MindMaster posted:

black holes are made up



are you talking about rupaul

#40
Communism just seems right to me. It just...*feels* right, you know?